Category Archives: Psykologi

INFP – portræt og beskrivelse

Den passionerede og drømmende idealist, som respekterer andre og giver dem plads.

infp-150x150 Som INFP er din primære leveform fokuseret internt, hvor du beskæftiger dig med ting i henhold til, hvordan du føler om dem, eller hvordan de passer ind i dit personlige værdisystem. Din sekundære tilstand er ekstern, hvor du primært tager ting ind via din intuition.

INFP’er er fokuserede på at gøre verden til et bedre sted for mennesker. Deres primære mål er at finde ud af deres egen betydning i livet. Hvad er deres formål? Hvordan kan de bedst tjene menneskeheden i deres liv? De er idealister og perfektionister, der kører sig selv hårdt i deres søgen efter at nå de mål, de har identificeret for sig selv.

INFP’er er meget intuitive omkring mennesker. De er stærkt afhængige af deres intuition til at vejlede sig, og de bruger deres opdagelser til konstant at søge efter værdi i livet. De er på en kontinuerlig mission for at finde sandhed og meningen i tilværelsen. Hvert møde og hvert stykke viden bliver sigtet gennem INFP’ens værdisystem og vurderes for at se, om det har nogen muligheder for at hjælpe INFP’en med at definere eller forfine sin egen vej i livet. Målet for enden af ​​stien er altid det samme – det er, at INFP’en er drevet til at hjælpe mennesker og gøre verden til et bedre sted.

INFP’er er generelt eftertænksomme og hensynsfulde, og de er også gode til at lytte. Selv om de kan være reserverede og have svært ved at udtrykke følelser, har de en meget dyb omsorg og er virkelig interesserede i at forstå andre mennesker. Denne oprigtighed registreres af andre, hvilket gør INFP’en til en værdsat ven og fortrolig. En INFP kan være ganske varm i selskab med folk, som han eller hun kender godt.

INFP’er kan ikke lide konflikter og vil gå meget langt for at undgå dem. Hvis de skal se en konflikt i øjnene, vil de altid nærme sig den fra deres følelsers perspektiv. I konfliktsituationer kan INFP’er undertiden lægge meget lidt vægt på, hvem der har ret, og hvem der tager fejl. De fokuserer i stedet på, hvad konflikten får dem til at føle, og ikke på hvorvidt de rent faktisk har ret. De ønsker ikke at føle sig dårligt tilpas. Dette træk hos dem kan undertiden synes irrationelt og ulogisk i konfliktsituationer. Men på den anden side gør det INFP’er til gode mæglere, og de er typisk gode til at løse andre folks konflikter, fordi de intuitivt forstår folks perspektiver og følelser og oprigtigt ønsker at hjælpe dem.

INFP’er har meget høje standarder og er perfektionister. Derfor er de som regel hårde ved sig selv og sætter deres lys under en skæppe. INFP’er kan have problemer med at arbejde på et projekt i en gruppe, fordi deres standarder sandsynligvis vil være højere end andre gruppemedlemmers. Der må en INFP arbejde på at balancere sine høje idealer med kravene, som opstår i forbindelse med dag-til-dag-arbejde. Uden at løse denne konflikt vil de aldrig være tilfredse med sig selv, og de kan blive forvirrede og lammede over, hvad de skal gøre med deres liv.

INFP’er er ofte talentfulde forfattere. Det kan være akavet og ubehageligt for dem at udtrykke sig verbalt, men de har en fantastisk evne til at definere og udtrykke hvad de føler på papir. INFP’er optræder også ofte i social- og service-erhverv, såsom terapi eller undervisning. De er bedst i situationer, hvor de arbejder for almenvellet, og hvor de ikke behøver at bruge hård logik.

Hvem deler du type med? Se listen over berømte INFP’er her.

Emneord: Jungs Typer, Personlighedstyper, Jungianske Typer, Personlighedstests.

ENFJ – portræt og beskrivelse

Den givende mentor og coach, der får andre til at føle sig godt tilpas og leder fællesskabet frem mod nye mål og værdier.

enfj-150x150 ENFJ’er er fokuserede på mennesker. De lever i en verden af ​​menneskelige muligheder. Mere end nogen anden type, så har ENFJ’er fremragende færdigheder, hvad angår mennesker. De forstår og bekymrer sig om mennesker, og de har et særligt talent for at få det bedste frem i andre. ENFJ’ers hovedinteresse i livet er at give kærlighed, støtte og positive oplevelser til andre mennesker. De er fokuserede på at forstå, støtte og opmuntre andre. De får ting til at ske for folk, og de får personlig tilfredsstillelse af at hjælpe andre.

ENFJ’ers evner til at omgås folk er så usædvanlige, at de kan få folk til at gøre, præcis hvad ENFJ’en vil. De kommer ind under huden på folk, og de får de reaktioner, de søger fra andre. ENFJ’ers motiver er normalt uselviske, men ENFJ’er, der har udviklet sig mindre end ideelt, har været kendt for at bruge deres magt over mennesker til at manipulere dem.

ENFJ’er er så eksternt fokuserede, at det er særligt vigtigt for dem at tilbringe tid alene. Det kan være svært for nogle ENFJ’er at tage sig tid til at være alene, fordi de har tendens til at få mørke tanker, når de er alene. Derfor kan ENFJ’er nogle gange undgå at være alene og i stedet fylde deres liv med aktiviteter, der involverer andre mennesker. ENFJ’er har en tendens til at definere deres livs retning og deres egne prioriteter i henhold til andre folks behov. Somme tider er de ikke så opmærksomme på deres egne behov. Det er naturligt, at denne personlighedstype vil have tendens til at placere andres behov over sine egne, men ENFJ’er bør prøve at være opmærksomme på deres egne behov, således at de ikke ofrer sig selv i deres bestræbelser på at hjælpe andre.

ENFJ’er er på mange måder ekspressive og åbne, men de er mere fokuserede på at være lydhøre og støttende for andre end på at brage igennem med deres egne meninger. Når man står med en konflikt mellem selv at føre sig frem og så at lytte til en anden persons behov, så er de mere tilbøjelige til at lytte til den andens behov.

En ENFJ kan føle sig ensom, selv når han er omgivet af mennesker. Denne følelse af ensomhed kan blive forværret af hans tendens til ikke at afsløre sine sande holdninger, men i stedet altid være på udkig efter hvad andre nu har brug for.

Folk elsker ENFJ’er. De er sjove at være sammen med, og de forstår og elsker andre mennesker. ENFJ’er udstråler normalt en masse selvtillid og har en stor evne til at gøre mange forskellige ting. De er generelt kvikke, fulde af potentiale, energiske og tempofyldte. ENFJ’er kan godt lide, at ting er organiserede, og de arbejder hårdt på at fastholde struktur og på at komme af med tvetydighed.

På arbejdspladsen gør ENFJ’er sig godt i stillinger, hvor de beskæftiger sig med mennesker. De er naturligt hjemme i sociale udvalg, HR og hvad som helst, der har at gøre med mennesker. Deres uhyggelige evne til at forstå folk og sige lige, hvad der skal siges for at gøre dem glade, gør dem også gode til rådgivning. De nyder at være i centrum for opmærksomheden, og de gør meget godt i situationer, hvor de kan inspirere og motivere andre, såsom undervisning.

Generelt er ENFJ’er charmerende, varme, venlige, kreative og mangfoldige individer med et rigt udviklet indblik i, hvad der får andre mennesker til at tikke. Denne særlige evne til at se vækstpotentialet i andre kombineret med et ægte drive til at hjælpe folk gør ENFJ’en til et virkelig værdsat individ. Så givende og omsorgsfulde som ENFJ’er er, skal de huske at værdsætte deres egne behov såvel som andres behov.

Hvem deler du type med? Se listen over berømte ENFJ’er her.

Emneord: Jungs Typer, Personlighedstyper, Jungianske Typer, Personlighedstests.

Guide til MBTI / JTI / Jungs Typelære

Hvad betyder bogstaverne?

E eller I: Hvor kommer din energi fra?

I betyder ”Introvert”
Introverte mennesker får deres energi fra at være alene i stilhed. De har svært ved afbrydelser. De føler sig mere stimulerede til at være sociale og sammen med andre, efter de har haft lange stunder for sig selv.

E betyder ”Ekstrovert”
Ekstroverte mennesker får deres energi af at være sammen med andre og ”tænke højt ud i rummet.” De føler sig mere stimulerede til at samle deres tanker og arbejde igennem, efter de har været sociale.

S eller N: Hvilke typer informationer kan du bedst lide at arbejde med?

N betyder ”iNtuitiv”
Intuitive typer elsker at arbejde med teorier og muligheder – det, der kunne være, men som ikke er. Intuitive typer hopper rundt fra ting til ting, og fra emne til emne, som en astronom med et teleskop. N-typer er i reglen meget glade for abstraktion og kan nogle gange sidde og diskutere en ting med stor entusiasme. S-typer synes nogle gange, at N typer burde teoretisere mindre og gøre mere.

S betyder ”Sansende”
S-typer elsker at arbejde med sikre fakta og detaljer. Hvis N-typer er drømmende, er S-typer realistiske. De ved, hvad der er muligt, og hvordan man gør det. S-typer kan lide diskussioner med et klart afgrænset emnefokus og bryder sig ikke op at hoppe fra mulighed til mulighed – de foretrækker planer og handling, som man ved kan blive til noget i den virkelige verden.

F eller T: Hvordan træffer du beslutninger?

T betyder ”Tænkende”
Tænke-typer træffer beslutninger på baggrund af upersonlig logik. De lægger vægt på objektive informationer og parametre og kan af og til opleves som kolde og logiske af Føle-typer. Tænke-typer anvender ofte logik som deres rettesnor, når de argumenterer. T-typer lader sig styre af hovedet.

F betyder ”Følende”
F-typer træffer beslutninger på baggrund af deres personlige værdier og opfattelser. De er fuldt ud i stand til at anvende logik, når opgaven kræver det, men deres egentlige beslutningsgrundlag ligger i værdiernes verden. På trods af navnet er føletyper ikke direkte styret af deres følelser, men snarere af deres personlige værdier og sentimenter. F-typer lader sig føre af hjertet.

J eller P: Hvordan er din livsstil?

J betyder “Vurderende”
(J kommer fra det engelske “Judging”). J-typer holder af struktur og faste planer, og de er ofte gode til at sætte ydre opgaver i system. Når man står over for en stor opgave eller et stort projekt, kan det være stressende for J-typer ikke at vide, hvem der skal gøre hvad hvornår, eller hvad det næste punkt på dagsordenen er.

P betyder “oPfattende”
P-typer foretrækker at leve deres liv tilbagelænet, spontant og fleksibelt. P-typer er ofte gode til at improvisere og til at tage tingene, som de kommer. Når en beslutning skal træffes, kan en P-type føle, at det er kvælende at skulle lægge sig fast på en given løsning, så længe muligheden for at “vente og se hvad der sker” stadig er til stede.

Buddhist Ideas Explained

You can’t, beyond a few basic things, say that *all* Buddhists believe something, since Buddhism is like all of philosophy reinvented in its own image. There are sooo many Buddhist philosophers; Nagarjuna is just the greatest one. And Nagarjuna is very important to all Buddhists except for the ones in India/Sri Lanka and some of Cambodia.

*On top of that* you have religious Buddhism and philosophical Buddhism. Supposedly, the Buddha made fun of his followers for supposing that he was immortal, but then you get other sources saying that he was uniquely divine. I guess you rarely start anything spiritual in premodern times without being deified at least a bit. Even Nagarjuna was deified as being able to speak with snake-gods, and he is pretty rational.

Karma — In Hinduism, karma is like a cosmic accountancy system, governing the cycle of birth and death. This is what most We11sterners mean when they refer to karma. Some Buddhist texts are like this too, but in Buddhism, there is no caste system. Often, when the Buddha talks about karma, he means something more akin to “activity” or “causation.” Not in the sense of Western / Aristotelian ideas, but more like a descriptor of why the world (as he sees it) becomes more and more uneven or differentiated. Karma is not so much specific actions, which give you plus and minus points, as in Hinduism, but more like accumulated causation up to this point (to pre-Nagarjuna Buddhists). So, for example, for a European girl to have blond hair, there would have to be a massive accumulation of prior karma in the universe (big bang, apes, humans, Northern Europeans, etc.) that come together to determine that. It’s like a huge backlog of causation, to which you can add your own little speck. Because everything you do (and even think) has some kind of karma as well, adding to the molehill.

This is roughly what the Buddha taught. In religious Buddhism this then becomes construed to something more like what Hinduism was; — if you do the “good” things you will get a good “result” and have an easier time reaching nirvana. But the Buddha denied this, as did several famous pre-Nagarjuna monks. It was more of a folk belief.

Nagarjuna, of course, doesn’t need karma. He does not deny or affirm it; it’s is just empty of self-existed, co-caused by the universe and the universe co-caused by it..

Reincarnation — Depends on the branch and on philosophical/religious
Buddhism. People often ask: “If there’s no self in Buddhism, what is
reborn?” To pre-Nagarjuna (philosophical) Buddhists, what’s “reborn”
is actually the karma of the things you did — your little specks of
causation you added to the molehill, even though “you” are not there
anymore. A good pointer against the religious belief that you are
somehow reborn as something higher or closer to nirvana is the
Buddha’s own assertion that he was not immortal and would not be
reborn. But people believe what they will — a Thai Buddhist once told
me, that the most virtuous things to be reborn as in his order were:
1 Man
2 White elephant
3 Woman

XD

Though Chinese/Japanese Buddhism was hugely influenced by Nagarjuna,
they tend to downplay, or even be ignorant, of it. In some ways, those
branches go back to Buddha too. But they have a wordy disposition
where many of their masters write completely upfront that rebirth is
to be understood somewhat like a log consumed by flame still leaving
ashes – Dogen Zenji (Japanese guy) says burned logs don’t go back to
being logs again XD But I think even in China and Japan, the monks
don’t really rush to correct people in need of consoling fantasies of
literal rebirth.

Morality — Many Buddhists have some kind of morality. Compassion,
don’t hurt people, don’t cheat and lie, mmmkay. However, the Buddha
does not say that these are inherent truths about the universe. He is
actually pretty good on the is/ought on this point, even though Indian
thinkers don’t really think that kind of distinction makes sense. So
he says that it is only those *who wish to end the suffering that he
is speaking of* that should embark on that morality.
So the Buddha did postulate a certain morality. It was pretty fixed
and it was the intention that mattered (like Kant). But unlike Kant,
the Buddha also varied his own conduct depending on who heard his
sermons so maybe he broke his own precepts a bit XD
At any rate, the morality part has been overturned by many (but not
all) later Buddhists (even pre-Nagarjunists). There is a strong
tradition in Buddhism of “doing good brings no rewards”; “doing good
has no intrinsic value.” Some Buddhists (especially Indians) still
stick very closely to fixed precepts, but most don’t. Like the Dalai
Lama eating meat, or the zen masters beating up their own students.
Because fixed precepts don’t square so well with increased awareness
and the “mindfulness” you get in meditation, which is the *real* point
of Buddhism.

Meditation — This is where it’s at. Anyone can meditate and Buddhists
didn’t invent meditation. They were, however, the first ones (I think)
to say that everyone (who wished to cure the ills that the Buddha was
speaking of) should meditate and that meditation was kind of the point
of the whole thing. A lot of the other beliefs are just there to
support and mix with meditation. So, you don’t have to meditate, but
on the other hand, you can never understand the Buddhist teachings
fully if you don’t. There’s a realm of “intuitive knowledge,”
sometimes called the “dharma eye” because it’s unlike any other kind
of mental activity. It has nothing specific to do with Buddhism.
Hindus, Christians, Muslims etc. have such experiences too when they
meditate or engage in meditation-like behaviors. But Buddhism is
probably the only “religion” that takes the gist of these states and
builds the majority of its philosophy around that.

Enlightenment — The Buddha was enlightened in meditation, he saw the
truth about the universe with the “dharma eye” and saw that it was
seeing this truth (“we’re all oooooneeee”) could liberate people from
“suffering.” By suffering we mean something more like the fact that
phenomenal existence is imperfect and conditioned and therefore bound
to cause dissatisfaction because we could easily imagine the imperfect
to be perfect and we get attached to the idea of wanted the phenomenal
to be perfect. To experience enlightenment is not only to see how it’s
all oooooneeee, but also to see how that order is really perfect just
as it is (so there is a ceasing of wanting and attachments). That is
why I said that in Indian philosophy, Is/ought does not make much
sense – is/seeming would make better sense where seeming is phenomenal
existence and is is nirvana.

So nirvana is not some “place” like heaven and paradise; it’s just a
glimpse, perhaps only a second-long glimpse, of the “true state of the
universe,” glimpsed through the dharma eye. And since the mental
contents of this faculty are inexpressible, they cannot form
scientific claims that conflict with scientific experiments, etc. —
all they can do is argue with scientists about what is the “is” and
what is the “seeming” on the is/seeming divide. Is it the vision of
nirvana that’s the greater truth and phenomena that are lesser, or is
nirvana a hallucination with phenomena being the truth. Some Chinese
Buddhists (Hua Yen) actually made a whole branch in the middle ages,
arguing that each truth — the spiritual and the phenomenal — were
equally important.

Oh yeah, and some Buddhist branches, such as Soto Zen, don’t regard
enlightenment as important at all. Such experiences such create a
series of new attachments, because people dream themselves back to the
moment of their “vision” instead of focusing on their meditation.
That’s where the Zen teacher breaks out the stick and hits the pupil
for not paying attention to the now 😀

“No self” claim — It means several things: It means that you don’t
have an immortal soul, as in Hinduism or some Christian theology, for
example. It also means that no part of the brain is the “self,” like
Hume also says. If you _really_ examine your mental life without
preconceptions, you just experience a bundle of thoughts, feelings,
memories, fears, etc. – the “self” is a conventional belief that is
found not to have a direct, empirical basis in the faculties of
introspection.
“Life is suffering” claim — As said above. Suffering (dhukka) is more
like imagining/expecting the conditioned phenomena of existence to be
perfect when they can’t be: “Why am I not younger/smarter/richer/more
beautiful?” To stop this, the Buddha says that “the way” is to
meditate etc. as already mentioned. But it could be debated whether he
allows for there being other ways. Certainly, original Buddhism did
allow for people to keep their original religions and be Buddhist too.

Idealist/solipsism philosophy — Only Yogacara is solipsist/idealist.
The Buddha is actually something of an empiricist where it’s the
(inherently unstable) physical entities that come together to create
the faculties of consciousness. He is not a materialist/physicalist,
but acknowledges that there’d be no consciousness without the physical
prerequisites. And he *also* hinted that reality, as we perceive it,
is co-created by the mind (although understandably, he did not exactly
say how).

Rejection of the world — the
earliest Buddhism, they sometimes had morbid practices like meditating
in graveyards, not having children, and giving up all possessions.
This was to avoid attachments to imperfect phenomena and only meditate
and think of that. But Buddha himself rejected asceticism, as do many
modern Buddhists; they say that asceticism is just as much as bias as
indulgence, so let go of both!

MBTI Personality Tests in Foreign Languages

The Myers-Briggs Type Indicator (MBTI) is the world’s most popular personality test. There are lots of free personality tests proposing to test one’s MBTI type online.  But most of them are not very scientific. These free, professional-grade MBTI tests are offered in foreign languages for your service and perusal. Have fun discovering your personality type and unique cognitive preferences in one of the languages below.

MBTI Two Types Tests

With MBTI types, people are often confused as to whether they are one or the other. CelebrityTypes.com offers a series of tests to help you find our what type you are, if you are confused over two types:

The Myers-Briggs or MBTI type test is the most popular personality test in the world and used by governments and Fortune 500 companies across the globe. While the test is popular and time-honored, it often happens that newcomers are confused over their type and have trouble determining their own type. To this end, these two-types test may provide a valuable guide and assistance in pointing the test taker in the direction of his true type.

Nina Fauerholdt, Lars Lundmann og personlighedstests

I WA IDEER 20. Marts skriver Nina Fauerholdt om psykolog Lars Lundmann, der har forsket i jobsamtaler. I artiklen hedder det bl.a., at det er de færreste mennesker, hvis personlighedstræk er stabile. Det er noget pjat.

Den såkaldte Fem-faktormodel, som der henvises til i artiklen er blevet forsket til døde af forskerhold fra hele verden, som har gjort brug af enorme datasæt hentet fra flere nationer. Gang på gang er det blevet konkluderet, at de overordnede personligehedstræk, som denne test måler, ligger overvejende stabilt omkring 15-årsalderen og er stort set urokkelige efter de 30.

I artiklen hedder det også, at personlighedstests ”kun bidrager med støj.” Pjat igen. Hvad angår jobsamtaler har videnskabelige undersøgelser konkluderet, at en persons resultater på Fem-faktormodellen er en kraftigere forudsigelse for hvordan vedkommende vil klare sig på jobbet end vedkommendes referencer fra tidligere arbejdspladser, tidligere joberfaring og uddannelsesniveau.

Epicurus, Poststructuralism, and Nāgārjuna as Sources of Eudemonia

By Ryan Smith

1 Reason: An enemy and enslaver or a friend and helper?

The ”destabilization” of facts, the resistance to categories of knowledge, the cult of the immediate, the ”non-hierarchical communities” (Foucault) all point towards a common poststructuralist project, namely the dismantling of classical humanism and the philosophical notion of the individual subject: As a phase in the “emancipation” from bourgeois norms, the individual must cast off all conceptions of identity, as these are just the machinations of an external bourgeois discourse that have been forced upon the individual. As Deleuze and Guattari would posit in Mille Plateaux (1980): “[We should aim to] reach, not the point where one no longer says I, but the point where it is no longer of any importance whether one says I. We are no longer ourselves.”[1]

This project of de-subjectification is but philosophical flotsam from Nietzsche’s “Dionysian impulse” as originally depicted in Die Geburt der Tragödie aus dem Geiste der Musik (1872) as well as from the subject-less Dasein of Martin Heidegger which simply just is.[2] This subjectlessness stands in the starkest possible contrast to the philosophical project of Socrates which constantly underlined the importance of continuously greater sophrosyne (wise self-insight) which is attained through critical introspection and gnōthi seauton (knowledge of the self).[3]

This approach to philosophical practice, however, would not reach its zenith with Socrates, but rather with Epicurus’ development of the original Socratic position. As we shall see, the Epicurean philosophy possesses an epistemology and an elaborate psychology of the subject which directly opposes the poststructuralist precept that the existence of the individual is derogated when tied up with rational categories of knowledge.[4] To the extent that the poststructuralists depict themselves as philosophers it seems quite odd that there does not exist a single poststructuralist refutation of Epicurus, for even in spite of the poststructuralist “de-centralization” of facts, the philosophy of Epicurus is at heart a unison of exactly the two things that poststructuralists believe to be irreconcilable: Rational knowledge and sensory happiness.[5]

According to Epicurus, man experiences happiness by understanding the material world rationally. Earthquakes are not the wrath of the gods, planets are not omens, and death is not eternal pain. Rationality is not the nemesis of human nature, but a friend and a helper.

2 Liberating the soul: Transgression versus Ataraxia

As an applied philosophy, and a way of life, Epicureanism, like poststructuralism, aims to liberate the individual by uncovering the hidden forces that coerce it. For Foucault, these are the so-called “techniques of knowledge and subjectification”[6], while for Lyotard ”The notorious universality of knowledge […] [is] a mark of the destruction of personal identities.”[7] Common to each of these approaches is the fact that they endeavour to challenge the primacy of the singular, cognizant individual (often called ‘the subject’). For Lyotard, dispassionate analysis is the arch nemesis of the subjective, sublime feeling that cannot be analysed and cannot be shared with others in the least.[8] While for Foucault there was the Bataille-inspired ‘Limit-experience’:[9] Experiences so intense that they scramble all individual cognisance and reveal analytical modes of thought as unreal derivatives of reality, rather than true reality. The sensation generated by the limit-experience, then, is what Foucault referred to as transgression.[10]

Common to each of these approaches, however, is that they are epistemologically untenable: For without the notion of a subject, how can Foucault and Lyotard know that the subject is curtailed by knowledge-categories and analytical modes of thought? Likewise, how can poststructuralists know that individual identity exists when there is no subject on which to pin it?

So according to poststructuralism impersonal knowledge restricts and fetters the individual and compels it; governs it to be inauthentic. (As Lyotard said, only the self that is free of contact with knowledge-categories is in fact a self.)[11] Faced with exactly the same problem, Epicureanism argues instead for a synthesis that makes use of knowledge-categories as a way to liberate the subject:

”Just as there is no use in medical expertise if it does not give therapy for bodily diseases, so too there is no use in philosophy if it does not expel the suffering of the soul.”[12]

According to Epicureanism, expelling the suffering of the soul will lead to ataraxia, that is, a state of mental ease which – ironically enough – corresponds extremely well to the sensation described in Foucault’s account of transgression. So while Epicureanism and poststructuralism could not be further from each other with regards to means, they are essentially the same with regards to ends: The existential condition craved by each of these philosophies is ultimately very similar.

Where they differ, however, is that ataraxia is achieved through rational and calm contemplation of the human conditions and the often harsh terms of life on Earth, whereas transgression is instead facilitated though extreme and destructive experiences: Crime, drugs, sexual and political violence. As Foucault said, everything short of the extreme is nothing:

”Those middle-range pleasures that make up everyday life … are nothing. … A Pleasure must be something incredibly intense. … Some drugs are really important … because they are the mediation to those incredibly intense joys.”[13]

Or as the very same thought was sloganistically expressed in Surveiller et punir (1975):

”The soul is the prison of the body.”[14]

Meaning essentially the soul as the reflecting Cartesian cogito and the body as immediate, unreflective modes of existence: Thus according to poststructuralism, the more the cogito reflects on impersonal, identity-compelling knowledge-categories, the more the immediate and subjective is coerced into objective inauthenticity.[15]

An argument along the same lines can also be found in Foucault’s earlier work,

Folie et déraison (1961): Having subjected madness to science (and dubbed it déraison), the West no longer fears folkloric madness (called folie) as a force with the potential to erupt into a pandemonium that can possess us all.[16] According to Foucault, science has dispelled the tenseful duality between sane order and mad chaos that had persisted from ancient times.[17] And consequently, life in the scientific episteme, that is, in the West, has become a bland and sterile unity.[18]

Such themes evoke parallels to Nietzsche’s early Die Geburt der Tragödie (1872) as well as the later Götzen-Dämmerung (1889). In Nietzsche’s rendition of events, the Apollonian and the Dionysian impulses are poised in equilibrium; they constantly curb and check each other, until sometime in the fifth century BCE the Apollonian gained the upper hand.[19] In Nietzsche’s narrative, the Apollonian without the Dionysian heralds the decline and decadence of Greek culture[20] and culminates in the perverse, ”wrong” Socrates who curtails Der Wille zur Macht (the Will to Power).[21] And what, according to Nietzsche, was the cardinal sin of Socrates’ philosophical endeavour? It was precisely that he sought to equip the Greeks with a self-consciousness that made use of objective knowledge-categories.[22]

Confronted with these same problems, the Epicurean posits instead that the greatest threat to ataraxia is the irrational fear that results from holding irrational beliefs.[23] (For example, believing that the reason that your house burned down is that Zeus is angry with you; this irrational belief leads to a constant irrational fear.) According to Epicurus, such irrational beliefs are best eradicated by the subject becoming acquainted with logic and material science and especially physics. Through an insight into science and epistemology the subject will eventually come to know that the celestial bodies above are not gods waiting to rain their wrath down upon you, but rather clouds of atoms; worlds such as this one.[24] To the poststructuralists discussed above such an approach to epistemology would lead to a convoluted Cartesian life, but to Epicurus it leads, fundamentally, to a life in accordance with nature.[25]

”What produces the pleasant life if not continuous drinking and parties of pederasty or womanizing or the enjoyment of fish and other dishes of an expensive table, but sober reasoning which … banishes the opinions that beset souls with the greatest confusion.”[26]            (boldface added)

Rational knowledge and categories of knowledge do not just compound with human happiness and the wise self-knowledge that is sophrosyne. According to Epicurus, rational deliberation and introspection is the very precondition for human happiness and thus an unbending affront to the central premise of the supposed need for the poststructuralist emancipation-project. For according to the poststructuralist view, the very rational deliberation that Epicurus would have us engage in, in order to set us free, provokes “existential anxiety” and prohibits the delight in the senses that leads to true happiness.

3 Which Position is more Epistemologically Tenable?

Finally, leaving the question of happiness, we will look into which position is more epistemologically tenable. To this end we will need to define what kind of knowledge we are inquiring into. To this aim, I will present a theory not entirely unlike that of Karl Popper’s classical Three-world Theory to help us discern which kind of knowledge we are talking about.[27] The three kinds of knowledge that I will posit for this purpose are Immediate knowledge, Existential knowledge, and Objective knowledge. We will now look into each in turn.

Immediate Knowledge: By ‘Immediate knowledge’ we mean somatic, subjective and phenomenological knowledge. For example, how do you subjectively experience the phenomenon of thirst; what personal psychological connotations do you attach to it; what unconscious associations does thirst whirl up in you? This kind of knowledge is profoundly personal to the point where it cannot be communicated onto others; indeed even if it could, doing so would border on meaninglessness as the knowledge is both idiosyncratic and so inwardly richly textured that any recounting of the experience onto the other would be but a pale shadow of one’s own Immediate knowledge of it.

Hence, with regards to the domain of Immediate knowledge, Epicurean epistemology falls rather flat: To Epicurus, fear of phenomena is always lurking around the corner; a rainbow may be beautiful, but it could also be an omen; a particular dish may be delightful, but it may also sow the seeds of avarice and obesity.[28] Thus the Epicurean ‘cure’ is always to distance oneself from subjective and personal experience and seek a rational, trans-personal explanation to put in the place of personal meaning.[29] Thus, Epicurean epistemology is the enemy of Immediate knowledge.

By contrast, however, Immediate knowledge is the stated soteriological goal of poststructuralist epistemology.[30] It is through the intense and boundary-absolving experience of immediate reality that one can really live as a subject-less, emancipated, indefinable agent.[31] As we have seen, crime, drugs, sexual and political violence are all acceptable (and at times, recommended) as means to the end that is the poststructuralist conception of Immediate knowledge. Indeed, as we saw from Foucault above, anything short of the extreme is nothing.[32] By the same token, that is also why, when Foucault was asked to characterize Jean-Paul Sartre’s philosophical project, with its somber system of personal ethics, the former had but one word for it: “Terrorism”.[33]

However, when examining the poststructuralist recipe for inquiring into Immediate knowledge, we should be aware of a crucial critical interjection: Why are the extreme limit-experiences perceived as holding the key to an immediate understanding of reality when the brunt of reality plainly does not consist of such experiences? Of course, as the poststructuralists would no doubt posit, this touting of the limit-experience as a source of truer knowledge is due to the fact that our everyday notion of reality is to some degree socially constructed, wherefore we should seek out experiences that are not associated with our everyday lives in order to steal a peek at what lies behind the web of social constructs – to de-construct it, so to speak.

Yet a pertinent rejoinder presents itself in the face of this response: How can reality be defined by marginal experiences that are not central to it? Indeed in other sciences, researchers are often encouraged to discard outliers, while poststructuralists would seem to accord value only to outliers. In the same vein, if one wanted to say something about human cognition, one would get a skewed picture if one only used the exceptionally bright and the exceptionally dull for data. There is a fundamental misnomer at work here, which is how and why it becomes reasonable to the post-structuralist to inquire into a thing solely by virtue of its extremes all the while ignoring the bulk of it. And after all, even in a life filled with limit-experiences, the everyday sensations of thirst, hunger, sleep, fiscal ruminations and sex will remain largely the same with regards to Immediate knowledge.

Existential knowledge: By ‘Existential knowledge’ we mean extant knowledge of reality as it exists and the psychological self-knowledge that can be derived from this type of knowledge in order to allow man to find a personally meaningful place in the universe and a sense of purpose in life. This knowledge is not entirely rational, but nor is it entirely irrational. Existential knowledge is not impersonal (like Objective knowledge; to which we will turn shortly), but nor it is entirely personal (like Immediate knowledge, with which we have just dealt). Naturally this “middle of the road” quality makes the exact properties of Existential knowledge hard to pin down, but in making the attempt, we will posit that Existential knowledge is a kind of psychological knowledge or insight into reality. It is the type of knowledge that we all use when we decide whether to pursue one prospective partner over another, or deciding whether to have (more) children or that the family is now of an adequate size. It is the type of knowledge of which the fruits are sophrosyne (wise self-insight) which is attained through critical introspection and gnōthi seauton (knowledge of the self).[34]

Now at first glance it might seem like poststructuralist epistemology would be a good source of Existential knowledge (after all, several of most prominent poststructuralist philosophers were the intellectual scions of the great French existentialists). But, inspired by the Indian philosopher Nāgārjuna (ca. 150–250 CE), we will argue that limit-experiences, of the kind trumpeted by poststructuralists, in fact constitute a hindrance to Existential knowledge.

According to Nāgārjuna, intense emotional experiences will not at all allow you to conceive reality any clearer than adherence to the rational cogito.[35] Both the insistence on rational knowledge (as trumpeted by Epicureans) and a familiarity with limit-experiences will, according to Nāgārjuna, ultimately distance your mind from the true nature of reality. But the poststructuralist approach will be the worse of the two, and for two reasons:

(1) Limit-experiences are so intense that they will tie your experience of reality to your own emotional life, whereas reality is far vaster than the personal subject. The poststructuralists claim that limit-experiences are so intense that they will dismantle the personal subject, but indeed, who has ever seen a shell-shocked soldier experiencing sudden bursts of universal empathy or an inexplicable experience of the vastness of the cosmos? Thus, limit-experiences will dismantle a person’s rational notion of his or her subject, but limit-experiences will not at all dismantle a person’s practical focus or groundedness in his or her own subject, quite the contrary; being shell-shocked, raped or cut with a knife (all examples of limit-experiences) will only serve to preoccupy a person all the more with his or her own well-being. Thus, as existence is obviously larger than one person’s pain or pleasure, limit-experiences will actually serve as a diminishment of Existential knowledge.

(2) By its very definition, a limit-experience is so intense that it will flood a person’s cognition with the derived effects of that particular experience. But a limit-experience is not something vast and multi-faceted; indeed it is usually of a quite singular nature. Conseuently going through a limit-experience will again diminish one’s ontological outlook. For example, let us say that a person is suspended in space, looking over Times Square in New York City: If he is stuck in the Epicurean cogito, he will see knowledge-categories walk by: Young/old, male/female, rich/poor, human, pigeon, dog and so on. If he is a follower of Nāgārjuna, he will see no categories, as he will pass no rational judgment (having relinquished the Epicurean cogito), and yet he will be keenly observant – he would indeed experience something like the transgressory state that limit-experiences supposedly lead to. However, if our observer is undergoing a limit-experience while watching the activity at Times Square – if he is simultaneously being subjected to intense physical pain, for example – our observer will surely not notice much of the activity in Times Square, as he will be completely overwhelmed by the limit-experience and thus attached to a narrow corner of existence rather than to existence itself.[36]

Thus poststructuralist epistemology is most certainly not a good source of Existential knowledge.

What about Epicurean epistemology as a source of Existential knowledge, then? As Nāgārjuna would have it, rational knowledge and knowledge-categories would also be a hindrance to existential knowledge yet not one that is nearly as bad.[37] If one’s primary approach to reality is through knowledge-categories (such as young/old, male/female, rich/poor, human, pigeon, dog etc.), then one is indeed depriving oneself of Existential knowledge as one would naturally miss all the idiosyncrasies and in-betweens that are present outside of the subject’s pre-conceived mental pigeonholes. But, as opposed to the limit-experience which, as we have seen, is a tyrant of the psyche, knowledge-categories at least constitute a reductionist model of reality and thus a broader outlook than the one provoked by the the limit-experience.

Thus, while poststructuralist epistemology as a source of Existential knowledge is decidedly poor, Epicurean epistemology is simply ok.

Objective knowledge: By ‘Objective knowledge’ we mean much the same as what Karl Popper meant by his Third World, that is, the state of our scientific and objective knowledge as it exists in books, letters, on discs, hard drives etc.[38] Without going into it here, we shall also assume, as did Popper, that the epistemology of the Third World is possible, even without a knowing subject.[39] This condition is not central to our argument, but it will help us unite our inquiry into Objective knowledge with the subject-less philosophy of poststructuralism.

4 Conclusion

While poststructuralism may indeed surpass the traditional Epicurean-Cartesian system with regards to auiring self-knowledge of one’s everyday persona, the poststructuralist adherence to the limit-experience is flawed as a source of Existential knowledge, and regarding objective, scientific knowledge, only the Epicurean-Cartesian system of rational knowledge will ultimately do.

Immediate Knowledge Existential Knowledge Objective Knowledge
Epicureanism Poor Ok Good
Poststructuralism Good Poor Poor

References
Ansell-Pearson, Keith: An Introduction to Nietzsche as Political Thinker: The Perfect Nihilist (Cambridge University Press 1994)
Bülow, Katharina von: Contredire est undevoir (Le débat September-October 1986)
Dean, Michell: Critical And Effective Histories: Foucault’s Methods and Historical Sociology (Routledge 1994)
Deleuze, G. & Guattari, F.: Thousand Plateaus – Capitalism and Schizophrenia (Continuum International Publishing Group 1994)
Dews, Peter: Logics of Disintegration: Post-structuralist thought and the claims of critical theory (Verso Books 2007)
Ferry, L. & Renaut, A.: French Philosophy of the Sixties (University of Massachusetts Press 1990)
Foucault, Michel: Abnormal: Lectures at the College De France 1974-75 (Verso Books 2003)
Foucault, Michel: Discipline & Punish: The Birth of the Prison (Vintage 1995)
Foucault, Michel: Madness and Civilization (Routledge 1995 ed.)
Foucault, Michel: Madness and Civilization (Routledge 2006 ed.)
Foucault, Michel: Religion and Culture (Manchester University Press 1999)
Foucault, Michel: The order of things: an archaeology of the human sciences (Routledge 2004)
Gutting, Gary (ed.): The Cambridge Companion to Foucault (Cambridge University Press 2005)
Heidegger, Martin: Being and Time (Blackwell Publishers 1974)
Kelly, Michael: Critique and Power: Recasting the Foucault / Habermas Debate (The MIT Press 1994)
Lyotard, Jean-François: Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime (Stanford University Press 1994)
Lyotard, Jean-François: Libidinal Economy (Continuum 2004)
Lyotard, Jean-François: The Postmodern Condition (Manchester University Press 1984
Miller, James: The Passion of Michel Foucault (Harvard University Press 2000)
Nāgārjuna: Nagarjuna’s Letter to a Friend: With Commentary by Kyabje Kangyur Rinpoche (Snow Lion Publications 2005)
Nietzsche, Friedrich W.: Writings from the Early Notebooks (Cambridge University Press 2009)
Nietzsche, Friedrich W.: Writings from the Late Notebooks  (Cambridge University Press 2003)
Nietzsche, Friedrich W.: The Birth of Tragedy out of the Spirit of Music (Cambridge University Press 1999)
Nietzsche, Friedrich W.: The Will to Power (Random House 1973)
Nietzsche, Friedrich W.: Twilight of the idols, or, How to philosophize with the hammer (Oxford University Press 2009)
Oksala, Johanna: Foucault on Freedom (Cambridge University Press 2005)
Popper, Karl R.: Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach (Oxford University Press 1979)
Rabinow, Paul (ed.): Ethics, Subjectivity and Truth, ed. (The New Press 1997)
Scott, G.A.: Does Socrates Have a Method?: Rethinking the Elenchus in Plato’s Dialogues and Beyond (Pennsylvania State University Press 2004)
Simons, Jonathan: Foucault and the Political (Routledge 1995)
Warren, James: Facing Death – Epicurus and his Critics (Oxford University Press 2004) pp. 155-6

Ancient Sources
Epicurus: The Four-Part Cure
Epicurus: The Letter to Pythocles
Epicurus: The Letter to Menoeceus
Epicurus: The Sage as an Ethical Role Model
Nāgārjuna (attributed): Hymn to the Dharmadhātu
Nāgārjuna: Letter to a Friend
Plato: Apology
Plato: Symposium
Plato: Theaetetus
Porphyry: The Letter To Marcella

NOTES

[1] Deleuze, G. & Guattari, F.: Thousand Plateaus – Capitalism and Schizophrenia pp. 3-4

[2] Heidegger, Martin: Being and Time p. 150, pp. 165-6, cf. Ferry, L. & Renaut, A.: French Philosophy of the Sixties p. 214

[3] Plato: The Theaetetus 210bc, cf. The Apology 29b, cf. The Symposium 218bc, cf. Scott, G.A.: Does Socrates Have a Method?: Rethinking the Elenchus in Plato’s Dialogues and Beyond pp. 204-7

[4] Foucault, Michel: Madness and Civilization (Routledge 1995 ed.) p. 287

[5] Dews, Peter: Logics of Disintegration: Post-structuralist thought and the claims of critical theory p. 259, cf. Foucault, Michel: “Michel Foucault: An Interview by Stephen Riggins“, featured in Rabinow, Paul (ed.): Ethics, Subjectivity and Truth, ed. p. 129

[6] Foucault, Michel: Discipline & Punish: The Birth of the Prison pp. 127-131 cf. Dean, Michell: Critical And Effective Histories: Foucault’s Methods and Historical Sociology pp.164-167, cf. Kelly, Michael: Critique and Power: Recasting the Foucault / Habermas Debate pp. 269-271

[7] Lyotard, Jean-François: Libidinal Economy p. 249

[8] Lyotard, Jean-François: The Postmodern Condition, §15. The full quote will convey the author’s intent: “A self does not amount to much, but no self is an island; each exists in a fabric of relations that is now more complex and mobile than ever before. Young or old, man or woman, rich or poor, a person is always located at ‘nodal points’ of specific communication circuits, however tiny these may be.” That is supposedly to say: Only through the relinquishment of analytical knowledge-categories can the individual truly be himself. For further examples, see: Lyotard, Jean-François: Lessons on the Analytic of the Sublime pp. 238-239

[9] Foucault, Michel: The order of things: an archaeology of the human sciences p. xxvi cf. Foucault, Michel: Religion and Culture p. 23, cf. Miller, James: The Passion of Michel Foucault p. 32

[10] Foucault, Michel: A Preface to Transgression in Foucault, Michel: Religion and Culture pp. 57-72, and Foucault, Michel: Madness and Civilization (Routledge 2006 ed.) pp. 249-254, and Foucault, Michel: Abnormal: Lectures at the College De France 1974-75 pp. 173-4, cf. Gutting, Gary: The Cambridge Companion to Foucault p. 22, cf. Simons, Jonathan: Foucault and the Political pp. 69-70,

[11] Lyotard, Jean-François: The Postmodern Condition, §15

[12] Porphyry: The Letter To Marcella, 31

[13] Foucault, Michel: “Michel Foucault: An Interview by Stephen Riggins“, featured in Rabinow, Paul (ed.): Ethics, Subjectivity and Truth, ed. p. 129

[14] Foucault, Michel: Discipline & Punish: The Birth of the Prison p. 30

[15] In Foucault’s rendition of the scientific episteme, van Gogh would supposedly need doctors’ permission to paint paintings. Foucault, Michel: Madness and Civilization (Routledge 2006 ed.) p. 203, 273

[16] Foucault, Michel: Madness and Civilization (Routledge 2006 ed.) p. 223

[17] Foucault, Michel: Madness and Civilization (Routledge 2006 ed.) pp. 100-101

[18] Foucault, Michel: Madness and Civilization (Routledge 2006 ed.) pp. 263-4

[19] Nietzsche, Friedrich W.: The birth of tragedy out of the spirit of music §22

[20] Nietzsche, Friedrich W.: The birth of tragedy out of the spirit of music, An Attempt at Self-Criticism §1, cf. Appendix, §2

[21] Nietzsche, Friedrich W.: Twilight of the idols, or, How to philosophize with the hammer, cf. Nietzsche, Friedrich W.: The birth of tragedy out of the spirit of music, §13 cf. Nietzsche, Friedrich W.: Notebook Entry, KSA 8.97, 6: “Socrates … I am constantly doing battle with him.”, cf. Nietzsche, Friedrich W.: The Will To Power, §432

[22] Ansell-Pearson, Keith: An Introduction to Nietzsche as Political Thinker: The Perfect Nihilist pp. 67-68

[23] Epicurus: The Four-Part Cure (“Do not fear God / Do not Worry about death / What is good is easy to get / and what is terrible is easy to endure.”), cf. Letter To Pythocles, 110, 111, cf. The Letter to Menoeceus, 124, 132, 133, cf. Warren, James: Facing Death – Epicurus and his Critics pp. 155-6

[24] Epicurus: Letter To Pythocles, 88, 89, 96, 97, 112

[25] Epicurus: The Letter to Menoeceus, 128, 133, cf. The Sage as an Ethical Role Model, 118-120

[26] Epicurus: The Letter to Menoeceus, 131

[27] Popper, Karl R.: Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach, chapters 3 and 4.

[28] Epicurus: The Letter to Pythocles, 98, 109, cf. Letter to Menoeceus, 132-133

[29] Epicurus: The Letter to Pythocles, 85

[30] Foucault, Michel: The order of things: an archaeology of the human sciences p. xxvi cf. Foucault, Michel: Religion and Culture p. 23, cf. Miller, James: The Passion of Michel Foucault p. 32

[31] Foucualt, Michel, quoted in Oksala, Johanna: Foucault on Freedom p. 129

[32] Foucault, Michel: “Michel Foucault: An Interview by Stephen Riggins“, featured in Rabinow, Paul (ed.): Ethics, Subjectivity and Truth, ed. p. 129

[33] Foucault, Michel, quoted in Bülow, Katharina von: Contredire est undevoir p. 177

[34] Plato: The Theaetetus 210bc, cf. The Apology 29b, cf. The Symposium 218bc, cf. Scott, G.A.: Does Socrates Have a Method?: Rethinking the Elenchus in Plato’s Dialogues and Beyond pp. 204-7

[35] Nāgārjuna: Nagarjuna’s Letter to a Friend: With Commentary by Kyabje Kangyur Rinpoche p. 33, 93, 96, 150

[36] As we have seen, the poststructuralists claim that you cannot be free whilst experiencing the world through the rational cogito, but they fail to explain how one can be free while undergoing an arbitrary limit-experience. In the world of knowledge-categories there are at least several different categories to choose from, whereas in the world of limit-experiences there is only one limit experience at a time. The poststructuralist might argue that one can choose what type of limit-experience one would subject oneself to, thereby constituting a similar multitude of options, but how could a person choose between different types of limit-experiences without relying on knowledge-categories in the first place?

[37] This will be my argument, but I believe it fairly evident from passages such as Nāgārjuna’s Hymn to the Dharmadhātu, verse 6, trans. Donald Lopez in Lopez, Donald S., Jr. (ed.): Buddhist Scriptures (Penguin Books 2004) p. 466

[38] Popper, Karl R.: Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach p. 107

[39] Popper, Karl R.: Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach pp. 115-117